Applications


A new kind of city science built on living structure and on the third view of space*

Mar 2022 | No Comment

The new city science aims not only to better understand geographic forms and processes but also – maybe more importantly – to make geographic space or the Earth’s surface living or more living

Bin Jiang

Professor, Faculty of Engineering and Sustainable Development, Division of GIScience University of Gävle, SE- 801 76 Gävle, Sweden

Abstract

The third view of space states that space is neither lifeless nor neutral, but a living structure capable of being more living or less living, which was formulated by Christopher Alexander under the organismic world view that was first conceived by the British philosopher Alfred Whitehead (1861–1947). The living structure is defined as a physical and mathematical structure or simply characterized by the recurring notion (or inherent hierarchy) of far more small substructures than large ones. The more substructures the more living or more beautiful structurally, and the higher hierarchy of the substructures the more living or more beautiful structurally. This paper seeks to lay out a new kind of city science on the notion of living structure and on the third view of space. The new city science aims not only to better understand geographic forms and processes but also – maybe more importantly – to make geographic space or the Earth’s surface living or more living. We introduce two fundamental laws of living structure: Tobler’s law on spatial dependence or homogeneity and scaling law on spatial interdependence or heterogeneity. We further argue that these two laws favor statistics over exactitude, because the statistics tends to make a structure more living than the exactitude. We present the concept of living structure through some working examples and make it clear how a living structure differs from a non-living structure. In order to make a structure or space living or more living, we introduce two design principles – differentiation and adaptation – using two paintings and two city plans as working examples. The new city science is a science of living structure, dealing with a wide range of scales, from the smallest scale of ornaments on walls to the scale of the entire Earth’s surface.

* The title was inspired by Stephen Wolfram’s A New Kind of Science, which is a generative science using cellular automata, but the book or cellular automata in general never discusses goodness or quality of generative patterns or structure. The paper directly confronts the goodness or quality of structure, arguing that it is a matter of measurable or quantified fact rather than opinion or personal preferences.

1. Introduction

The great architect Christopher Alexander had some remarkable insights about architecture, which applies equally to geography. Over the past century, geography (or architecture) has always been a minor science, seeking application of the physical sciences such as physics and anthropology. In the next two centuries, geography (or architecture) might become a major science, a sort of complexity science, when the deep question of space has been properly understood (Grabow 1983). The deep question touches the very nature of space or the organismic view of space, as formulated by Alexander (2002–2005, 1999), that space is neither lifeless nor neutral but a living structure capable of being more living or less living. Living structure is such a structure that consists of far more small things (or substructures) than large ones across all scales ranging from the smallest to the largest (scaling law, Jiang 2015), yet with more or less similar sized things (or substructures) on each of the scales (Tobler’s law 1970). It is initially the deep question or the very notion of living structure or the organismic view of space that triggered us to develop this paper.

The third view of space differs fundamentally from the first two views of space: Newtonian absolute space and Leibnizian relational space, which are framed under Cartesian mechanistic world view (Descartes 1637, 1954). The mechanistic world view is so dominated in science and in our thinking as if it were the only mental model, or even worse it may be considered to the world itself. It is a powerful model about our world, for what we human beings have achieved in science over the past hundred years is largely attributed to the mental model. However, the mechanistic mental model is limited when comes to design or creation, as the goodness of designed or created things is sidelined as an opinion or personal preference rather than a matter of fact (Alexander 2002–2005). Under Newtonian absolute and Leibnizian relational views of space – a geographic space is represented as a collection of geometric primitives such as points, lines, polygons, and pixels (c.f., Figure 2 for illustration), which tend to be “cold and dry” (Mandelbrot 1982), so it is not seen as a living structure.

The mechanistic world picture has two devastating results according to Alexander (2002–2005). The first was that the “I” went out of the world picture and the inner experience of being a person is not part of this picture. The second was that the mechanistic world picture no longer has any definite feeling of value in it, or value has become sidelined as a matter of opinion rather than as something intrinsic to the nature of the world. The organismic world picture first conceived by Whitehead (1929) extends the mechanistic world picture to include human beings as part of the organismic world picture. The same world view has been advocated by quantum physicist David Bohm (1980) among many others. Under the organismic world view, we human beings are part of the world rather than separated from the world. In other words, the physical world or the universe is organism like rather than machine like (Whitehead 1929). It is under the organismic world picture that Alexander (2002–2005, 1999) formulated the third view of space. Under the third view of space, value lies on the underlying configuration of space, and the goodness of space is no longer conceived as a matter of opinion, but a matter of fact. The shift from the opinion view to the fact view or from the mechanistic world view to the organismic world view represents something fundamental (Kuhn 1970) in our thinking about geography, for design or how to make living or livable space is at the forefront of geographic inquiry.

We in this paper attempt to setup city science on the notion of living structure and on the third or organismic view of space, leading to a new kind of city science or new city science. Living structure is said to be governed by the two fundamental laws: the scaling law (Jiang 2015) and Tobler’s law (1970). Among the two laws, the scaling law is the first, or dominant law, as it is universal, global, and across scales, while Tobler’s law is available locally or on each of the scales. Conventionally, city science or the new science of cities (Batty 2013) has been viewed as a minor science or an applied science that seeks to apply major sciences for understanding geographic forms and processes. In this paper, we argue that the new city science is a major science, a science of living structure, not only for understanding geographic forms and processes, but also for making and remaking geographic space or the Earth’s surface towards a living or more living structure. The remainder of this paper is organized as follows. Section 2 introduces the two fundamental laws of living structure that favors statistics over exactitude. Section 3 illustrates how living structure differs from non-living one under two different world views. Section 4 presents two design principles differentiation and adaptation in order to make or transform a space to be living or more living. Section 5 further discusses the new city science and its deep implications. Finally in Section 6, the paper concludes with a summary pointing to a prosperous future of the new city science.

2. Two statistical laws together for characterizing living structure

The notion of living structure applies to all organic and inorganic phenomena in the scales ranging from the smallest Planck’s length to the largest scale of the universe (Alexander 2002–2005, 2003), so do the scaling law and Tobler’s law. The applicability implies that there are far more small particles than large ones, far more rats than elephants, far more small stars than large ones, far more small galaxies than large ones, and so on. This paper deals with a range of scales of the Earth’s surface between 10^-2 and 10^6 meters. The Earth’s surface is governed by two fundamental laws: the scaling law and Tobler’s law, as mentioned at the outset of this paper. Table 1 shows how these two laws complement rather than contradict to each other from various perspectives (Jiang and Slocum 2020). It is wise to keep the scaling law as the dominant one, as it is global or across scales, whereas Tobler’s law is local or on each scale. In conventional city science or the new science of cities, Tobler’s law is usually overstated as the first law of geography, and it implies that the Earth’s surface is in a simple and well-balanced equilibrium state. However, we know that the Earth’s surface is unbalanced and very heterogeneous and every place is unique (Goodchild 2004). Dominated by the scaling law or the non-equilibrium character, the new city science aims not only to better understand the complexity of the Earth’s surface, but also to make the Earth’s surface a living or more living structure. For creating living structures, two design principles – differentiation and adaptation – will be presented later on.

Unlike many other laws in science, these two laws are statistical rather than exact. The statistical nature is more powerful than the exactitude one. Below, we cite three sets of evidence in science and art to make it clear why exactitude is less important. First, Zipf’s law (1949) is also statistical rather than exact. It states that in terms of city sizes, the largest city is about twice as big as the second largest, approximately three times as big as the third largest, and so on. Here twice, three times, and so on are not exact, but statistical or roughly. Among the two sets for example: [1, 1/2, 1/3, …, 1/10] and [1 + e1, 1/2 + e2, 1/3 + e3, …, 1/10 + e10] (where e1, e2, e3, … e10 are very small values), the first dataset does not follow Zipf’s law, while the second does. Zipf’s law is a major source of inspirations of fractal geometry (Mandelbrot 1982). In his autobiography, Mandelbrot (2012) made the following remark while describing the first time he was introduced to a book review on Zipf’s law: “I became hooked: first deeply mystified, next totally incredulous, and then hopelessly smitten … to this day. I saw right away that, as stated, Zipf’s formula could not conceivably be exact.” A dataset following Zipf’s law meets the scaling law, but not vice versa, which means that the scaling law is even more statistical than Zipf’s law. Zipf’s law requires a power law while the scaling law does not.

The second evidence is not only statistical, but also geometrical. The leaf vein shown in Figure 1 (Jiang and Huang 2021) apparently has far more small substructures than large ones from the largest square to the smallest white spots. Carefully examining the structure of the leaf vein, it is not difficult to find that there are four different levels of scale according to thickness of their outlines. In contrast, the Sierpinski carpet also has far more smalls than larges; that is, far more small squares than large ones, exactly rather than statistically (Sierpinski 1915). Let us carefully examine the exactitude of the carpet. The largest square in the middle of the carpet is size 1/3, which is surrounded by eight squares of size 1/9, each of which is surrounded by eight squares of size 1/27, each of which is surrounded by eight squares of size 1/81. Thus, there are two exponential data series, each of which is controlled by some exact number. The size of squares is exponentially decreased by the exact number 1/3: (1/3, 1/9, 1/27, 1/81), whereas the number of squares is exponentially increased by the exact number 8: (1, 8, 64, 512). Clearly there are far more small squares than large ones exactly rather than statistically. Because of the exactitude, the Sierpinski carpet is less living structurally than the leaf vein.

French painter Henri Matisse (1947) made a famous statement about the essence of art: “Exactitude is not truth”. In terms of exactitude, a photo is far better than a painting. However, the value of a painting lies not in its exactitude, but in something else, which is not only inexact, but also distorted or exaggerated. The distorted or exaggerated nature is often used in drawing a cartoon. A human face is a living structure governed by the scaling law and Tobler’s law, with the recurring notion of far more smalls than larges. The eyes, nose, mouth, and ears are the largest features and are therefore the most salient; each of them – if examined carefully – is a living structure again, with the recurring notion of far more smalls than larges. All human faces are universally beautiful in terms of the underlying living structure, despite some tiny cultural effects on their beauty. The scaling law and Tobler’s law are really two fundamental laws about livingness or beauty.

They can be used to examine many patterns or structures (e.g., Wade 2006, Wichmann and Wade 2017) for understanding not only why they are beautiful, but also how beautiful they are. For example, the leaf vein is living or beautiful because of the recurring notion of far more small structures than large ones. This way, through these two laws, the livingness or beauty of a structure or pattern can be objectively or structurally judged. Importantly, the livingness judged through these two laws can be well reflected in the human mind and heart, thus evoking a sense of beauty. This point will be further discussed in the following.

3. Living versus nonliving structure: The “things” the two laws refer to

The two laws introduced above have a common keyword – “things”: (1) more or less similar things on each scale, and (2) far more small things than large ones across all scales. What are the “things” the two laws refer to? In general terms, the things that collectively constitute a living structure are the right things, whereas the things that collectively do not constitute a living structure are not the right things. For example, if the leaf vein was saved as a gray-scale image with 1024 by 1024 pixels, each of which has a gray scale between 0 and 255, careful examination of these pixel values would show that they do not have far more light (or dark) pixels than dark (or light) ones. This way, we would end up with an absurd conclusion that the leaf vein is not a living structure. In fact, the pixels are not the right things, or the pixel perspective is not the right perspective for seeing the living structure.

In addition to the perspective discussed above, the scope also matters in seeing a living structure. A tree has surely far more small branches than large ones across scales from the largest to the smallest, while branches on each scale are more or less similar. Thus, the tree is no doubt a living structure, not biologically but in terms of the underlying structure. However, its leaves can be both living and non-living structure depending on the scope we see them. It is a living structure, if we go down to the scope or scale of intra-leaves, each of them has multiple scales (as shown in Figure 1). It is a nonliving structure, if we on the other hand concentrate on inter-leaves, they are all more or less similar sized, being the smallest scale of the tree. In addition, the leaf vein shown in Figure 1 is not a complete leaf, but part of it, with the large enough scope for us to see the living structure. All geographic features are living structures, if they are seen correctly with the right perspective and scope.

Let us further clarify the term “things” or substructures through two working examples: A street network and a coastline (Figure 2, Jiang and Slocum 2020). Conventionally, in geography, the things often refer to geometric primitives such as pixels, points, lines, and polygons.

It is little wonder that Tobler’s law is seen pervasively, as there are more or less similar sized things seen from the perspective of geometric primitives. For example, a street network has more or less similar street segments, or all the street junctions have more or less similar numbers of connections (1–4) (Figure 2a). A coastline consists of a set of more or less similar line segments (Figure 2c). Unfortunately, all these geometric primitives are not the right things for seeing the street network or coastline as a living structure. There is little wonder, constrained by the geometric primitives, that living structure was not a formal concept in geography or city science.

A street network is more correctly conceived of as a set of far more short streets than long ones, or a set of far more less connected streets than well connected ones (Figure 2b). The street network has four levels of scale, indicated by the four colors, far more short streets than long ones across the scales, and more or less similar streets on each of the four scales. A coastline is more correctly represented as a set of far more small bends than large ones (Figure 2d). The coastline has three levels of scale, indicated by three sets of bends: [x1], [x2, x3], and [x4, x5, x6, x7]. The notion – or recurring notion – of far more smalls than larges should be the major criteria for whether things are the right things that enable us to see a living structure, or whether we have the right perspective and scope for seeing a living structure.

The “things” that collectively constitute a living structure are also called centers (Alexander 2002–2005), a term that was initially inspired by the notion of organisms conceived by Whitehead (1929). Centers or organisms are the building blocks of a living structure, and their definitions are somewhat obscure. Instead, in this paper we use substructures to refer to the right things for seeing a living structure. This way, a living structure can be stated – in a recursive manner – as the structure of the structure of the structure, and so on. The things or substructures constitute an iterative system. To make the point clear, it is necessary to introduce the head/tail breaks (Jiang 2013), a classification scheme for data with a heavy-tailed distribution.

For the sake of simplicity, we use the 10 numbers [1, 1/2, 1/3, …, 1/10] to show how they are classified through the head/ tail breaks (Figure 3, Jiang and Slocum 2020). The dataset is a whole, and its average is about 0.29, which partitions the whole into two subwholes: those greater than the average are called the head [1, 1/2, 1/3], and those less than the average are called the tail [1/4, …, 1/10]. The average of the head subwhole is about 0.61, and it partitions the head subwhole into two subwholes again: those greater than the average are called the head [1], and those less than the average are called the tail [1/2, 1/3]. Instead of expressing the dataset as a set of numbers, we state the 10 numbers as an iterative system consisting of three subwholes recursively defined: [1], [1, 1/2, 1/3], and [1, 1/2, 1/3, …, 1/10]. Instead of perceiving these numbers as a set of 10 numbers, we consider them as a coherent whole, consisting of three subwholes including the whole itself. Or alternatively, these numbers as a coherent structure consists of three substructures including the structure itself. The dataset [1, 1/2, 1/3, …, 1/10], because of its inherent hierarchy of 3, is more living than the other dataset [1, 2, 3, …, 10] that is without any inherent hierarchy, or violates the notion of far more smalls than larges.

Now let us apply the recursive way of stating a whole or structure into the street network illustrated in Figure 2. Seen from above, the sample street network consists of 50 streets at four hierarchical levels indicated by the four colors: red (r), yellow (y), turquoise (t) and blue (b). Instead of stating the street network as a set or as four classes, we state it as an iterative system consisting of four subwholes or substructures that are recursively defined: [r], [r, y1, y2], [r, y1, y2, t1, t2, t3, t4, t5], and [r, y1, y2, t1, t2, t3, t4, t5, b1, b2, b3, …, b42]. In the same way, it is not difficult to figure out the three recursively defined subwholes for the coastline: [x1], [x1, x2, x3], and [x1, x2, x3, …, x7]. This living structure representation is recursive and holistic, so it differs fundamentally from existing representations that tend to focus on segmented individuals or mechanistic pieces. An advantage of the living structure representation is that the inherent hierarchy of space is obvious. To this point, we have seen clearly how the right things constitute an iterative system, being a living structure consisting of far more smalls than larges.

4. Two design principles: differentiation and adaptation

In line with the two laws of living structure, there are two design principles – differentiation and adaptation – for transforming a space or structure to be living or more living. The purpose of the differentiation principle is to create far more small substructures than large ones, while the adaptation principle ensures that the created substructures are well adapted to each other, e.g., nearby substructures are more or less similar. These two design principles ensure that any geographic space would become living or more living from the current status. Importantly, goodness of a geographic space is considered as a fact rather than an opinion, as mentioned above. These two design principles are what underlie the 15 structural properties (Figure 4) distilled by Alexander (2002–2005) from traditional buildings, cities and artifacts. The 15 structural properties can be used to transform a space or structure into living or more living structure. Interested readers should refer to Alexander (2002–2005), specifically Volumes 2 and 3, for numerous examples. In this section, we use two working examples – two paintings and two city plans – to clarify these two design principles.

The two paintings shown in Figure 5 are not very living, as they meet only the minimum condition of being a living structure with three or four inherent hierarchical levels. Painting (a) by Dutch painter Piet Mondrian (1872–1944) is entitled Composition II, with the three colors of red, yellow, and blue, whereas painting (b) is modified slightly from painting (a) by the author (Jiang and Huang 2021). Figure 5 demonstrates that how these two paintings are evolved – in a step-by-step fashion – from an empty square. Structurally speaking, painting (b) is more living than painting (a). It can equally be said that structure (g) is more living than structure (f), which is more living than (e), which is more living than structure (d), which is more living than structure (c). Thus, among all these structures or substructures, the empty square is the deadest, while structure (g) is the most living. On the one hand, there is the recurring notion of far more newborn substructures than old ones; on the other hand, within each iteration there are far more small substructures than large ones. Seen from the comparison, it is not hard to understand that one structure is – objectively – more living than another.

The goodness or livingness of a space – or a city in particular – is a matter of fact rather than an opinion or personal preference, based on the underlying living structure. More specifically, the goodness of a space depends on substructures within the space, as we have already seen in the above discussion. The goodness also depends on larger space that contains the particular space. This way of judging goodness or order of things is universal across all cultures, faiths, and ethnicities, not only for natural things, but also for what we make or build. This is probably the single most important message in the masterful work The Nature of Order (Alexander 2002–2005, 2003). This is a radical departure from the current view of space in terms of its goodness, judged by various technical parameters such as density, accessibility, and greenness.

The living structure constitutes the foundation of the new kind of city science this paper seeks to advocate and promote. The living structure perspective implies that a geographic space is in a constant evolution from less living to living or more living. Importantly, a geographic space or its design and planning process is an embryo-like evolution rather than LEGOlike assembly of prefabricated elements (Alexander 2002–2005, Jiang and Huang 2021). Note that the evolution view differs fundamentally from the assembly view, with the former being organic or natural, while the latter being mechanical or less natural. The living structure perspective implies also that a structure or substructures must be seen recursively. For example, conventionally painting (a) is seen as composed of 7 pieces, but it is more correct to say it consists of 18 (1 + 4 + 6 + 7) recursively defined structures or substructures (Figure 5). Instead of being 9 pieces for painting (b), it is more correct to say that it consists of 20 (1 + 4 + 6 + 9) recursively defined structures.

Using the recursive perspective, it is not hard to understand why traditional city plans are usually more living than modernist counterparts. For example, with the city of London plan, the notion of far more small substructures than large ones recurs five times, so there are 6 hierarchical levels, whereas for the Manhattan one, the notion of far more small substructures than large ones recurs twice, so there are only 3 hierarchical levels (Figure 6). Thus, the city of London city plan is more living – structurally or objectively – than the Manhattan one. There have been many human perception tests supporting the conclusion that traditional city plans are more living than modernist counterparts (e.g., Alexander 2002–2005, Wu 2015), indicating over 75% agreement between the human perception and the reasoning based on the two laws. There may be some people (fewer than 25%) who prefer modernist buildings because they look new and luminous or for whatever personal reasons. A recent biometric investigation (Salingaros and Sussman 2020) has provided further neuroscientific evidence that traditional façades are more “engaging” with people than contemporary façades.

Space has a healing effect, and this insight into space has been well established in the literature (e.g., Ulrich 1984). Human beings have an innate nature of loving lifelike things and processes such as forests and weathering. This affinity to nature is termed by the eminent biologist E. O. Wilson (1984) as biophilia. The biophilia effect has been used to help create living environments by integrating lifelike things such as light, water, and trees (Kellert et al. 2008). It should be noted that a true biophilia goes beyond the simple integration of natural things, but to create things that look like nature structurally (Salingaros 2015). Jackson Pollock (1912–1956) once said that he was not interested in mimicking nature, yet his poured paintings capture the order of nature. In this connection, living structure or the recurring notion of far more smalls than larges, as Alexander (2002–2005) has argued, appears to be the order that exists not only in nature, but also in what we make or build. The order – or living structure – constitutes the core or foundation of the new city science.

5. The new kind of city science, its implications, and future works

The new kind of city science or new city science laid down in the paper is established on the third view of space or on the solid foundation of living structure. The new city science is inclusive of a wide range of conventional disciplines, including for example architecture, urban design and planning, geography, and regional science, all to do with how to transform our cities and communities to be more livable, more living or more beautiful. Thus, the new city science is a science of living structure, not only for understanding geographic forms and processes, but also – more importantly – for making and remaking geographic space to be living or more living (i.e., sustainable spatial planning or design). Table 2 lists the differences between the new science of cities (Batty 2013) and the new kind of city science. The new city science goes beyond the two cultures under which science is separated from art (Snow 1959), towards the third culture (Brockman 1995) under which science and art is one. In the rest of this section, we further discuss on implications of the new City Science and future works to be done.

It is important to note that the concept of living structure is part of physics, part of mathematics, and part of psychology. As a physical phenomenon, living structure pervasively exists in physical space or in any part of space or matter, and the physical phenomenon constitutes part of physics, or part of quantum physics to be more precise rather than that of classic physics. In this connection, living structure has another name called wholeness that is essentially the same as implicate order (Bohm 1980). Living structure can be defined mathematically, but the mathematics is a nonlinear mathematics rather than a linear mathematics. The physical or mathematical structure can be psychologically or cognitively reflected in the human mind and heart, triggering a sense of livingness or beauty. Living structure is to livingness or beauty what temperature is to warmness. Given this, human related research such as spatial cognition, mental map, human way-finding, and even perception of beauty must consider the underlying living structure.

The new city science has huge implications on design and art, because goodness of art or design is no longer considered to be an arbitrary opinion or personal preference, but a matter of fact. It is essentially the underlying living structure that evokes a sense of goodness or beauty in the human mind and heart. Thus, there is a shared notion of quality or goodness of art among people or different peoples regardless of our culture, gender, and races. Goodness can be measured and quantified mathematically, and the outcome has over 70% agreement with people perception (e.g., Wu 2015, Salingaros and Sussman 2020). In this regard, the mirror-of-theself experiment (Alexander 2002–2005) provides an effective measure for testing people on their judgement on goodness of things. In this experiment, two things or pictures (for example, those pairs in Figures 1 and 6) are put side by side and human subjects are asked to provide their personal judgment to which one they have a higher degree of belonging or wholeness. The experiment is not kind of psychological or cognitive tests that seek inter-subjective agreement, but rather on degree of livingness, something objective or structural. This kind of experiment, as well as eye-tracking and other biometrics data (Sussman and Hollander 2015), will provide neuroscientific evidence for living structure, thus being an important future work in the new city science.

The new city science is a science of living structure, substantially based on living structure that resembles yet exceeds fractal geometry (Mandelbrot 1982). Like the new science of cities, fractal geometry belongs to the camp of mechanistic thought. For example, the commonly used box-counting method for calculating fractal dimension is too mechanical, as the boxes defined at different levels of scale are not the right things (or the right perspective) for seeing living structure (cf., Section 3). As we have illustrated in Figures 1 and 2, we adopt an organismic rather than mechanistic way of seeing living structures. Fractals emerge from an iterative process, but the iterative process is often too strict or too exact. The real world is indeed evolved iteratively, but it is not as simple as fractals, neither classic fractals nor statistical fractals. Nature – naturally occurring things – has its own geometry, which is neither Euclidean nor fractal, but a living geometry that “follows the rules, constraints, and contingent conditions that are inevitably encountered in the real world” (Alexander 2002–2005). The major difference between fractal and living geometries lies probably on the two different world views. More importantly, goodness of a shape is not what fractal geometry concerned about, but it is the primary issue of living geometry. Geographic information gathered through geographic information technologies has provided rich data sources for studying living structures on the Earth’s surface from the perspectives of space, time, and human activities. This is particularly true for big data emerging from social media or the Internet. The big data are better than government owned or defined data for revealing the underlying living structure for two main reasons. First, big data have high resolution (like GPS locations of a couple of meters), and finer time scales (down to minutes and seconds for social media location data). Thus, they are better than government data for seeing living structure at different levels of scale. Second, government-defined spatial units, such as census tracts, are too rough or too arbitrary for seeing living structure. Instead, we should use naturally defined spatial units such as natural cities and auto-generated substructures (Jiang 2018, Jiang and Huang 2021), which are all defined from the bottom up, rather than imposed from the top down, thus making it easy to see living structures. While working with big data, we should try to avoid using grid-like approaches such as the digital elevation model. Although the digital elevation model has far more low elevations than high ones, the grid approach is not the right perspective for seeing living structures. Instead, we should use watersheds or water streams which are naturally or structurally defined. All these topics will be studied in the future for the new city science.

6. Conclusion

This paper is intended to help set city science on the firm foundation of living structure, based on the belief that how to make and remake livable spaces – or living structures in general – should remain at the core of city science. Considering a room, for example, we should first diagnose whether it is a living structure. If not, try to make it a living structure; if it is already, try to make it more living. This pursuit of living or more living structure extends from our rooms, gardens, buildings to streets, cities, and even the entire Earth’s surface. City science should not just be a minor science – as currently conceived under the Cartesian mechanistic world view – that seeks to apply other major sciences or technology for understanding geographic forms and processes (or city structure and dynamics in particular). This is because these major sciences have not yet solved the problem of how to do an effective making or creation. Instead, the problem of making or creating is commonly left to art, design, or engineering, where there is a lack of criteria for judging the quality or goodness of the created things. In this paper, city science is built on the criteria of living structure, not only for understanding geographic forms and processes, but also for transforming geographic space to be living or more living.

The new city science is founded on the third or organismic view of space, under which space is conceived as neither lifeless nor neutral, but a living structure capable of being more living or less living. The third view of space reveals that the nature of geographic space is a living structure or coherent whole, and its livingness or the degree of coherence can be quantified by the inherent hierarchy or the recurring notion of far more smalls than larges. Throughout this paper, we have attempted to argue that the scaling law should play a dominant role for it is universal, global, and across scales, whereas Tobler’s law is available on each of these scales. These two laws are the two fundamental laws of living structure. To make a space living or more living, we must follow the two design principles or, more specifically, a series of biophilia design principles or the 15 structural properties. There are three fundamental issues about a geographic space (or a city in particular): (1) how it looks, (2) how it works, and (3) what it ought to be. The short response to these three issues is that a geographic space should look and work like a living structure and ought to become living or more living. Facing various challenges of our cities and environments, the new City Science provides new concepts, questions, and solutions to tackle problems and to make and remake cities and communities to be more livable and more beautiful towards a sustainable society. It is time to transform the new science of cities into the new kind of city science, a science of living structure for the Earth’s surface.

Acknowledgement

This paper is a reprint of the open-access one (Jiang 2021) but in a condensed manner for further advocating the new kind of city science. I would like to thank the anonymous referees and the editor A-Xing Zhu for their constructive comments. In addition, Yichun Xie, Jia Lu, and Ge Lin read an earlier version of this paper, and Chris de Rijke helped with part of the figures. Thanks to you all. This project is partially supported by the Swedish Research Council FORMAS through the ALEXANDER project with grant number 2017-00824.

References:

Alexander C. (2002–2005), The Nature of Order: An essay on the art of building and the nature of the universe, Center for Environmental Structure: Berkeley, CA.

Alexander C. (1999), The origins of pattern theory: The future of the theory, and the generation of a living world, IEEE Software, 16(5), 71–82.

Alexander C. (2003), New concepts in complexity theory: Arising from studies in the field of architecture,http://natureoforder.com/ library/scientific-introduction.pdf.

Bak P. (1996), How Nature Works: The science of self-organized criticality, Springer-Verlag: New York.

Batty M. (2013), The New Science of Cities, The MIT Press: Cambridge, Massachusetts. Bohm D. (1980), Wholeness and the Implicate Order, Routledge: London and New York.

Brockman J. (1995), The Third Culture: Beyond the Scientific Revolution, Touchstone: New York.

Christaller W. (1933, 1966), Central Places in Southern Germany, Prentice Hall: Englewood Cliffs, N. J.

Descartes R. (1637, 1954), The Geometry of Rene Descartes, translated by Smith D. E., and Latham M. L, Dover Publications: New York.

Goodchild M. (2004), The validity and usefulness of laws in geographic information science and geography, Annals of the Association of American Geographers, 94(2), 300–303.

Grabow S. (1983), Christopher Alexander: The search for a new paradigm in architecture, Oriel Press: Stocksfield.

Jiang B. (2021), Geography as a science of the Earth’s surface founded on the third view of space, Annals of GIS, x(x), xx–xx.

Jiang B. (2013), Head/tail breaks: A new classification scheme for data with a heavy-tailed distribution, The Professional Geographer, 65 (3), 482–494.

Jiang B. (2015), Geospatial analysis requires a different way of thinking: The problem of spatial heterogeneity, GeoJournal, 80(1), 1–13.

Jiang B. (2018), A topological representation for taking cities as a coherent whole, Geographical Analysis, 50(3), 298–313.

Jiang B. (2019), Living structure down to earth and up to heaven: Christopher Alexander, Urban Science, 3(3), 96. Reprinted as the cover story in the magazine Coordinates, March and April issues, 29–38, 12–17, 2020.

Jiang B. and Huang J. (2021), A new approach to detecting and designing living structure of urban environments, Computers, Environment and Urban Systems, 88, 1–10.

Jiang B. and Slocum T. (2020), A map is a living structure with the recurring notion of far more smalls than larges, ISPRS International Journal of Geo-Information, 9(6), 388.

Kellert S. R., Heerwagen J. and Mador M. (2008), Biophilic Design: The Theory, Science and Practice of Bringing Buildings to Life, John Wiley & Sons, Inc.: Hoboken, New Jersey.

Kuhn T. S. (1970), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, second edition, enlarged, The University of Chicago Press: Chicago. Mandelbrot B. B. (1982), The Fractal Geometry of Nature, W. H. Freeman and Co.: New York.

Mandelbrot B. B. (2012), The Fractalist: Memoir of a Scientific Maverick, Pantheon Books: New York.

Matisse H. (1947), Exactitude is not truth, in: Flam J. D. (1978, editor), Matisse on Art, E. P. Dutton: New York, 117–119.

Salingaros N. A. (1995), The laws of architecture from a physicist’s perspective, Physics Essays, 8, 638–643.

Salingaros N. A. (2015), Biophilia and Healing Environments: Healthy principles for designing the built world, Terrain Bright Green, LLC: New York.

Salingaros N. A. and Sussman A. (2020), Biometric pilot-studies reveal the arrangement and shape of windows on a traditional façade to be implicitly “engaging”, whereas contemporary façades are not, Urban Science, 4(2), 26, https://www.mdpi.com/2413-8851/4/2/26

Simon H. A. (1996), The Sciences of the Artificial (Third edition), The MIT Press: Cambridge, Massachusetts.

Sierpínski W. (1915), Sur une courbe dont tout point est un point de ramification, Comptes rendus hebdomadaires des séances de l’Académie des Sciences, 160, 302–5.

Snow C. P. (1959), The Two Cultures and The Scientific Revolution, Cambridge University Press: New York.

Sussman A. and Hollander J. B. (2015), Cognitive Architecture: Designing for how we respond to the built environment, Routledge: London.

Tobler W. (1970), A computer movie simulating urban growth in the Detroit region, Economic geography, 46(2), 234–240.

Ulrich R. S. (1984), View through a window may influence recovery from surgery, Science, 224, 420–422.

Wade D. (2006), Symmetry: The ordering principle, Wooden Books: Bloomsbury, USA.

Whitehead A. N. (1929), Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology, The Free Press: New York.

Wichmann B. and Wade D. (2017), Islamic Design: A Mathematical Approach, Birkhauser: Cham, Switzerland.

Wilson E. O. (1984), Biophilia, Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA.

Wu J. (2015), Examining the New Kind of Beauty Using Human Beings as a Measuring Instrument, Master Thesis at the University of Gävle.

Zipf G. K. (1949), Human Behaviour and the Principles of Least Effort, Addison Wesley: Cambridge, MA.

1 Star2 Stars3 Stars4 Stars5 Stars (No Ratings Yet)
Loading...


Leave your response!

Add your comment below, or trackback from your own site. You can also subscribe to these comments via RSS.

Be nice. Keep it clean. Stay on topic. No spam.